I continue the sketch of the basic features of visual artworks with a brief consideration of representation. Just as David Summer’s conception of visual artworks as real metaphors allows for expansion of Michael Podro’s account of artistic meaning as sustaining recognition so that the actual spatial placement of the work can be reckoned as part of its artistic meaning, the introduction of the concept of representation here into our conceptual resources will permit a finer-grained account of artistic meaning than is possible with Summer’s account. Summers treats the representative dimension of artworks under the term ‘image’, and restricts consideration of the image to its fundamental conceptualization as a substitution (as discussed in a previous post and as initially formulated in E. H. Gombrich’s account of the hobby horse), as seen in the following, his fullest statement on images in artworks: “in the broadest conditional terms, images are fashioned in order to make present in social spaces what for some reason is not present. Images do not simply represent, rather they inevitably make present in determinate ways, situating, continuing and preserving. Moreover, if images place or re-place the absent, their uses are always defined by present purposes. Images, in short, are put in social spaces, in determinate sizes, in order in some way to complete the social spatial definitions and differentiations” relevant to artistic meaning (Summers, p. 252). So we must look elsewhere for recognition and analysis of the representational dimension of depiction and visual artworks generally.
There is a very large philosophical literature in English on this topic, much of it quite technical, that arises from the critical reception of the philosopher Richard Wollheim’s criticisms of Gombrich’s account of ordinary experience of seeing a visual depiction, recognizing what is depicted, and further recognizing that it is a depiction, and not, say, a face to face encounter with the thing depicted. So in a simple case, one sees a piece of paper with some inked lines on it, and one sees a lion depicted by those lines. We say that the paper is a picture of a lion, and/or that it represents a lion, and/or that the ink drawing is a visual representation or depiction of a lion. Gombrich asserts that in the ordinary perception of the picture the viewer is aware of either the image (which he sometimes calls the ‘illusion’) or the paper and ink, but not both simultaneously. In a lengthy series of writings spanning the mid-1960s until his death in 2003, Wollheim made the counter-assertion that the ordinary perception of a picture involved a simultaneous awareness of the depicted subject and the material features of the support. In a canonical essay in the late 1970’s, Wollheim characterized the perceptual capacity exercised in pictorial experience as ‘seeing-in’, an irreducibly complex experience of seeing-something-in-something, so in our case of seeing-a-lion-in-a-marked-surface, and in Painting as an Art asserted that representation as given in the experience of seeing-in is one of the basic kinds of artistic meaning in painting. The academic literature on seeing-in, which includes a daunting range of agreements, disagreements, counter-proposals, and qualifications, as far as I can tell very largely ignores Wollheim’s own interest in representation as part of artistic meaning, and instead focuses on whether seeing-in can reasonably be thought to characterize the seeing of a trompe l’oeil painting, and whether Wollheim has sufficiently specified what it is to see a pictorial ‘image’ (the lion), whether and in what sense the ‘image’ is spatial and located spatially, and the relationship between the seeing of the ‘image’ and the seeing of the material support. The major exception has been Michael Podro, whose philosophical disagreement with Wollheim turns on their differing conceptions of the imagination and its role (limited for Wollheim, fundamental for Podro) in artistic seeing. So, as I have done previously, for the investigation here I can set aside much of this literature and draw points highly selectively insofar as they are relevant to specifying artistic meaning.
From this academic literature I limit myself to two helpful bits of descriptive terminology. The first comes from Wollheim himself, and the basic distinction it marks has been taken up by others, albeit in some cases with slightly different technical formulations. In conceptualizing the object of pictorial perception qua the twofold experience of seeing-in, Wollheim has distinguished two ‘folds’ (or aspects or dimensions), the recognitional fold and the configurational fold. The recognitional fold is what is seen as part of the ‘image’ (or ‘illusion’ or ‘virtual presence’); the configurational fold is the object of pictorial perception, but experienced as the perception of a marked surface. The second term, originating with Podro, is ‘inflection’, and is meant to gather those instances of pictorial perception wherein some feature or features of the configurational fold affect the perception of the recognitional fold. So one speaks of uninflected and inflected experience of pictures (see Nanay in the References below), with the seeing of a trompe l’oeil painting as the paradigm of the former,
and the seeing of Rembrandt’s etching of Jan Cornelisz Sylvius as exemplary of the latter.
With regard to the Rembrandt, Podro writes that the shadow of Sylvius’s hand “extends over the represented frame and we are led to wonder how far across the surface the fiction extends, and even, perhaps, where within our experience the shadow turns into mere ink” (Podro, p. 16) Podro notes that this is an instance of the phenomenon of ‘sustaining recognition’ wherein the knowledge that one is looking at a representation, a ‘fiction’, is put to use in enhancing the realization of the (recognized) subject. Podro adds a further astonishing insight, one that will play a fundamental in my own account of ornamentation as a basic kind of artistic meaning, that sustaining the recognition in this case is bound to two features (Podro calls them ‘motifs’) of borders between what is focally present to visual perception and something beyond it: the ‘real-fictive border’, with its metaphorization as “the boundary between the immanent world and the divine, and by extension between the living and the dead”; and further the “recurrent challenge to transcend the merely visual”. All of this is in the service of sustaining, enriching, and vivifying the metaphor, one exemplified by this work itself, that artistic vision is “transcending literal vision” (p. 17)
Most of the recent discussions of inflection do not seem to me to add anything fundamental to the account given by Podro and discussed at some length earlier in this book. The major substantive contribution comes from the philosopher John H. Brown, who discusses not inflection per se but a basic aspect of it, what he calls (following Hopkins (1998)), ‘separation’ phenomena. Quoting Wollheim (2001), Brown notes that with regard to any representational picture, there will be one or more things that can be ‘seen-in’ it, and additionally there will be other things seen that are not part of the subject and its properties. These latter are separation phenomena, and Brown claims that they play roles in any advanced pictorial seeing. There are two classes of such phenomena: one includes what has been introduced above under the term ‘configurational fold’, “the surface design as such” (Brown, p. 213); the other, which Brown calls ‘spatial separation seeing-in’ (p. 221), is everything involved in reducing something given in three-dimensional perception to something rendered in two dimensions. Brown lists seven features distinctive of picture-viewing: it lacks ordinary vision’s “selective clarity and blur”; it lacks “stereoscopic accommodation for distance”; there is no parallax within depicted scenes; the subject seems to deform from non-optimal points of view; pictorial space is discontinuous from the viewer’s ecological space; pictorial viewing lacks reduced acuity of distal perception; and picture-viewing “yields reduced illumination compared with face-to-face viewing of counterparts” (p. 222). Brown notes (quite rightly to my mind) that the factors involved in both kinds of separation seeing are insufficiently taken into account in most writing on the visual arts.
These bits of technical terminology—recognitional fold, configurational fold, inflection, and separation phenomena—provide, so I suggest, the needed conceptual resources that will allow us to describe and analyze the ways in which artistic meaning arises in the visual arts. Having considered composition and representation as part of the internal complexity of visual artworks, I now turn to the initial (historical, and perhaps also conceptual) elaboration of the artwork with one of the most pervasive features of visual artworks, ornamentation .
References and Works Consulted:
John H. Brown, ‘Seeing Things in Pictures’, in Philosophical Perspectives on Depiction (2010), ed. Abell and Bantinaki
E. H. Gombrich, Art and Illusion (1960)
Robert Hopkins, Picture, Image, and Experience (1998)
--‘Inflected Pictorial Experience: Its Treatment and Significance’, in Philosophical Perspectives on Depiction (2010), ed. Abell and Bantinaki
John Hyman, The Objective Eye (2006)
Dominic Lopes, Understanding Pictures (1996)
--Sight and Sensibility (2005)
Bence Nanay, ‘Inflected and Uninflected Experience of Pictures’, in Philosophical Perspectives on Depiction (2010), ed. Abell and Bantinaki
Michael Podro, Depiction (1998)
David Summers, Real Spaces (2003)
Alberto Voltolini, A Syncretistic Theory of Depiction (2015)
--‘Pictorial Experience and Aesthetic Appreciation: Wollheim Reassessed and Vindicated’, in The Pleasure of Pictures: Pictorial Experience and Aesthetic Appreciation (2019)
Richard Wollheim, ‘Seeing-as and Seeing-in’, in Art and Its Objects: with six supplementary essays (1980)
--Painting as an Art (1987)
--‘On Pictorial Representation’, in Richard Wollheim on the Art of Painting: Art as Representation and Expression (2001), ed. van Gerwen