The previous considerations of body and hand as resources of artistic meaningfulness aimed inter alia to bring to view two foundational aspects of the making and the species-wide intelligibility of the arts. First, and above all, the orientational aspects of embodiment—near/far, up/down, front-back, inside/outside—together with image schemas and basic experientialist conceptualizations provide a major part of the universal content and structures in the visual arts. Second, the account of projection, as applied to and across the distinction between peri-personal and extrapersonal space, opens the explication of how artistic meaning is formed in the processes of artistic making. Additionally, Tallis’s account of how the conceptualization of the hand retroacts upon the prior conceptualization of the body is a first instance of the holistic and open-ended quality of meaningfulness that will come to illuminate the basic characteristics of the inexhaustibility and (as yet unmentioned) ineffability of artistic meaning. In this post on gesture, and in succeeding posts on artifactuality, making, and technics, the guiding concern will be to provide the basis of another fundamental feature of artistic meaning, what the philosopher Patrick Maynard, himself explicitly following up indications from Michael Podro, has called the phenomenon of the ‘twice over’. The concern to explicate this phenomenon will then guide my selective accounts of gesture and artifactuality.
The phenomenon of ‘twice over’ is a major way in which in Podro’s sense recognition is sustained. Recall Podro’s account of artistic meaning in the visual arts: “At the core of depiction is the recognition of its subject, and this remains so even when the subject is radically transformed and recognition becomes correspondingly extended; it remains so not because we seek the subject matter despite the complications of painting but because recognition and complication are each further by the other, each serves the other.” (Podro, p. 5) Now, in depiction there is the subject depicted, and there is the formative process whose result is the depiction. The viewer’s awareness of the formative process, an awareness of the mechanisms of depiction--the brush strokes, marks, manipulations of the hand, etc.--, and any aspect whatsoever of the formative process given to the viewer in perception or imagination, is an awareness of the complications of recognition. A central mark of artistic meaningfulness is that the viewer is induced to interrelate the subject recognized and the complications of recognition, which typically includes analogizing one to the other and/or projecting an aspect of one onto an aspect of another (p. 8). Since artistic marking is something done, a human action, is bears expressive qualities that Podro calls ‘impulse’ (p. 9) or ‘energy’ (p. 13).
Podro’s point is not easy to grasp abstractly, so consider one of his early examples:
Podro describes an instance the phenomenon of twice over here in Veronese’s ‘Allegory of Deceit’ with “the sense of the brush across the heavy weave canvas intimates the physical immanence of the woman’s back while the shifts from opaque to translucent paint give a sense of a visual density into which we look.” (ibid)
As the example suggests, the expressiveness of ‘impulse’ and ‘energy’ are not in their roles in artistic meaning not necessarily expressive of emotion, mood, or feeling, but rather more typically express aspects of the formative process, and indeed of elaborated or refined aspects of that process. But what reason do we have to think that the viewer of a visual artwork infers automatically from the recognition that the work is an artifact, the product of human action, something done and made, to the imputation of impulse and energy to aspects of the artwork? My suggestion is that the projection of species-wide aspects of gesture and artifactuality provide the inferential path.
So, what is gesture, and what are its projectable characteristics? Despite, or perhaps because of, the omnipresence of gesture in human life, it has only been the subject of sustained philosophical and anthropological reflection in recent decades, most notably in the fundamental works of Adam Kendon and David McNeill. Surprisingly, the great work of André Leroi-Gourhan Gesture and Speech (originally 1964) offers little on gesture aside from noting that it becomes possible in hominid evolution with bipedalism, and that in the course of human history the hand becomes freed from tasks of direct grasping and manipulation through the development of tools and machines; the communicative dimension of gesture is wholly neglected. For Kendon, McNeill, and most recent thinkers, the orienting observation is that most human speech is accompanied by gestures. McNeill treats the definition of gestures as unproblematic and contents himself with the thought that gestures are “spontaneous movements”, “usually movements of the arms and hands” that “are closely synchronized with the flow of speech” (McNeill (1992), p. 11). For Kendon the elementary temporal structure of gesture consists of three phases: the movement of the hand forward and away from the speaker; the stroke; and the return of the hand to quiescence (p. 25).
McNeill finds five great categories of gestures: iconic (pictorial); metaphoric (iconic, but presents an abstract idea); beats (quasi-rhythmic, where the hand “moves along with the rhythmical pulsation of speech”; (cohesives (“serves to tie together thematically related but temporally separated parts of the discourse”); deictics (pointing to indicate objects and events in the concrete world, but also to an abstract concept related to a place). (pp. 12-18) McNeill further follows Kendon in ordering types of gesture in a continuum from gesticulation (gesture in the prototypical sense) to increasingly language-like movements: language-like gesticulation (as in “the parents were all right, but the kids were [gesture]”), then to pantomimes, emblems (conventional signs such as the ‘OK’ with the hand), and, at the far end of the continuum, sign languages (pp. 37-8).
I must defer discussion of the linguistic aspects of gesture until I have discussed language as a resource of artistic meaningfulness, but a bit more can be given now about non-linguistic gesticulation proper. McNeill notes two fundamental ways in which gesticulation differs from language in being global and synthetic. Gestures are global in the sense that the gesture as a whole is not composed out of parts that are themselves meaningful; rather the parts gain whatever meaning they have because of the meaning of the whole. For example, a speaker wiggles his fingers as he says “and he’s trying to run ahead of it” (p. 20). The gesture has parts by virtue of the elementary structure of gestures—the wiggling is part of the stroke--, but the parts are not independently meaningful. The gesture is synthetic in that it combines different (linguistically) meaningful elements: the wiggling of the fingers combines ‘he + running + along the wire’. (p. 21).
In light of McNeill’s example, I cannot resist recalling my introductory description of Warlpiri sand drawing; the reader will notice how a great deal of McNeill’s analysis readily applies to the analysis of the drawings. One need only supply the mechanism of projection, that is, that fundamental aspects of gesticulation—the global and synthetic, and the communicative dimensions of the iconic and the emblematic—to see the drawings as abstracted gesture.
In my next post I’ll turn to a lengthy consideration of the central manipulative and expressive uses of the hand in artifactuality and technics, and beginning with my most sustained attack on the hylomorphic model in its homeland, that is, in Aristotle’s account of artifacts in his Physics.
References and Works Consulted:
David Armstrong, William Stokoe, Sherman Wilcox, Gesture and the Nature of Language (1995)
Adam Kendon, Gesture: Visible Action as Utterance (2004)
André Leroi-Gourhan, Gesture and Speech (1993)
Patrick Maynard, Drawing Distinctions (2005)
Colin McGinn, Prehension (2015)
David McNeill, Hand and Mind: What Gestures Reveal About Thought (1992)
Michael Podro, Depiction (1999)
Raymond Tallis, The Hand: A Philosophical Inquiry into Human Being (2003)